Philosophy Notes Part 4
This is the fourth post in the Philosophy Notes series. Each post is a supplement to my philosophy study guides, a series of 8 books designed to help philosophy students read, understand, and think critically about the classics of philosophy.
Ethical Theory and the Limits of Philosophy
Immanuel Kant |
Proponents of analogical arguments from design for the existence of God cannot ignore conceptual analysis. After all, they must understand what they are looking for. But once they have clarified the key concepts used in their question, e.g. “Does God exist?” they go outside the concepts and introduce empirical facts in an attempt to solve what they take to be an inductive question. They are not restricted by certainty. Their path is not certainty but probability (hopefully strong probability) for their conclusions.
John Stuart Mill |
The justifications for universal moral rules are called ethical theories. There are two sets of ethical theories that head the long debate about right and wrong. The first group of theories is consequentialist. The only thing that matters in evaluating an act as right and wrong are the consequences of the act. The consequences are either good or bad, depending on how these evaluative words are defined. The motives of the actor (e.g. jealousy) and the name of the act (e.g. a lie, a broken promise) are irrelevant to a determination of right or wrong.
According to a version of the consequentialist theory called utilitarianism, a good consequence is identical with pleasure or happiness and a bad consequence is identical with pain or unhappiness. Thus, if I lie to you, my lie is justified if the total amount of pleasure is more than the total amount of pain. The lie, in and of itself, apart from its consequences, is neither right nor wrong.
“The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.” (Utilitarianism).
The second set of major ethical theories are referred to as deontological. A version of deontologism is Immanuel Kant’s categorical imperative. This theory is a direct contradiction to utilitarianism and all other consequentialist ethical theories. The theory says that our moral obligations are absolute. The imperative not to lie tells us categorically (unconditionally) that we must always tell the truth regardless of the consequences. Here is one statement of Kant’s imperative:
“So act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person or in another, always as an end and never as only a means.” (Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals)
Thus, even if the consequences of telling a lie are good, to tell a lie is to treat the person to whom you tell the lie merely as a means to an end. In effect, you are using that person to do something which that person has not consented to do.
Ethical theories are philosophical, not scientific. Scientific theories are tested by successful prediction of future events. Successful prediction is what justifies a scientific theory. For example, discoveries about the construction and transmission of the deadly coronavirus made it possible to predict that the spread of COVID-19 disease in unvaccinated communities will be significantly greater than the spread in vaccinated communities.
Philosophical theories are not created to make predictions. They are put forward to evaluate and guide human behavior. If philosophy is conceptual analysis, then what justifies a philosophical belief is to be found only in an analysis of the concepts that comprise the belief. This applies to beliefs about what is and what is not morally right or obligatory as much as it applies to any other philosophical belief.
A Simple Test to Determine Analytic Truth
There is a simple test to determine if this or any belief is analytically true. It is called the closed question test. It applies to questions about the relationship of concepts. For example, if it is analytically true that a bachelor is an unmarried male, then if someone were to ask “I know that John is a bachelor, but is he unmarried?” the answer is to be found in the question. The first part of the sentence “John is a bachelor” answers the second part. It makes no sense to ask the question in the first place unless the questioner is a young child or does not understand English. The question is both closed and senseless.
If the question is open, the answer is not to be found in the question. For example, if it is asked, “I know that John is a bachelor, but does John want to get married?” the first part of the sentence does not answer the second part. Moreover, the question is not senseless. The questioner can go outside the concept of ‘bachelor’ to determine what John wants or does not want. But if someone proposes that wanting to get married is a defining part of the word ‘bachelor,’ then their definition is analytically false. We know that it is false because one can sensibly ask the second part of the question (“does John want to get married?”).
In general, when we have an analytically true belief, the question we construct from the belief is both senseless and closed. When we have an analytically false belief, the question we construct from the belief is both sensible and open.
Let us apply this test to the two ethical theories described above, beginning with the utilitarian theory:
The utilitarian principle states the belief (qua principle) that an act is morally right if and only if it produces at least as much good (happiness) as bad (misery). If it produces more misery than happiness, then the act is morally wrong.
The test question for the utilitarian is: “Is the act that produces the greatest happiness for the greatest number the right thing to do?”
The question appears to be both sensible and open. If a defender of the utilitarian principle objects to this, there are several examples to which they can appeal. For example, suppose the lives of two young children can be saved by killing one elderly person. Suppose it can also be shown that this would produce more happiness than letting the children die (the combined happiness of the two children over the many years to come is greater than the happiness of one elderly person who probably has only a few more years to live). And yet despite this fact, it is reasonable to object that killing the elderly person without their consent is morally worse than saving the lives of the two children.
Because the test question is both sensible and open, Mill’s utilitarian principle is analytically false.
We turn now to the test question for Kant’s categorical imperative: “Is an act that treats humanity as a means, whether in my own person or in the person of another, morally right?”
Once again, as with the utilitarian principle, we find that the test question is both sensible and open. The example that comes to mind is one that was familiar to Kant and his critics. Suppose that I am hiding a frightened person in my house because a deranged man who wants to kill him is going door to door hoping to find him. He knocks on my door. I open the door and he asks whether the person they seek is inside. I reply by telling the lie “He is not in my house.” The would-be killer leaves and I have saved the life of my frightened guest.
This example proves that it is sensible to ask the question “Is it ever morally right to treat another person as a means to an end?” And it is an open question, the answer to which can only be found by going outside the concepts contained in the question.
Because the test question is both sensible and open, Kant’s Categorical Imperative, like Mill’s utility principle, is analytically false.
Keywords: Utilitarianism study guide,Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals study guide,John Stuart Mill study guide,Immanuel Kant study guide Utility principle,Greatest Happiness principle,Categorical Imperative,ethical theory, theories of ethics,moral theory,philosophical theory,philosophy definition,open questions,closed questions