Subscribe to our monthly Philosophy Newsletter and get a Free copy of Understanding Philosophy: The Smart Student's Guide to Reading and Writing Philosophy
Locke's Second Law of Nature
[This is the second in a series of posts for philosophy students who are doing their first reading of John Locke's Second Treatise of Government. The following passages are taken from my book Understanding John Locke: The Smart Student's Guide to Second Treatise of Government.]
Here is the paragraph in which Locke wrote the famous words that many years
later deeply influenced the political ideas of George Mason, John Adams, Thomas
Jefferson and other revolutionary British colonists in America:
The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it, which obliges
everyone: and reason, which is that law, teaches all mankind, who will but
consult it, that being all equal and independent, no one ought to harm another
in his life, health, liberty, or possessions (§6).
The obligations listed by Locke are all negative, that is they tell us what
we ought not to do, not what we ought to do. We ought to refrain
from harming others, but at the same time we are not told that we have
obligations to help others in achieving a better life, better health,
more liberty, or more possessions.
However, in the lengthy sentence that concludes §6 of Second Treatise,
Locke writes these words:
Everyone, as he is bound to preserve himself, and not to quit his
station willfully, so by the like reason, when his own preservation comes not
in competition, ought he, as much as he can, to preserve the rest of mankind,
and may not, unless it be to do justice on an offender, take away or impair the
life, or what tends to the preservation of the life, the liberty, health, limb,
or goods of another.
Locke here tells us that not only that we may not take away or impair the
life, liberty, health, limb, and possessions of others, but also that we
must protect and provide what “tends to the preservation” of these valuable
freedoms for all persons. This brief passage is not a mere
repetition of the first iteration of the law of nature. Locke repeats the
negative duties to not harm another person’s life, liberty, health and
possessions, but he also adds a positive duty to do whatever we can to
keep others alive, free and healthy.
This is perfectly consistent with Locke's earlier endorsement of Richard
Hooker’s claims about equality and the derived natural duties of justice and
charity. Hooker wrote that the equality of men by nature is “evident in
itself, and beyond all question.” Locke comments (in §5) that this
equality is “the foundation of the obligation to mutual love among men, on
which he [Hooker] builds the duties they owe one another, and from whence he derives
the great maxims of justice and charity”.
If we accept Hooker’s claim that all men are equal, then any duty that I
believe is owed to me, is also a duty that I owe to you. The word
“equality” implies equality of moral duties. If I say, for example, that
you have a duty to come to my aid in times of distress, then I imply that
everyone else has the same duty under the same circumstances:
For seeing those things which are equal, must needs all have one measure;
if I cannot but wish to receive good, even as much at every man’s hands as any
man can wish unto his own soul, how should I look to have any part of my desire
herein satisfied, unless myself be careful to satisfy the like desire?
(Hooker, Eccl. Pol. Lib. 1)
Locke points out that Hooker later derives “the great maxims of
justice and charity” from the concept of equality. This
ringing endorsement of Hooker gives us a new interpretation of
Locke’s law of nature. There are two laws of nature.
The first law tells us that we have a set of negative duties: not to harm one
another in our life, liberty, health or possessions. The second law says
that the basic obligations of equality and justice implies that we also have a
set of positive duties to do whatever we can to keep others alive, free and healthy.
The “community” to which Locke says we all belong in the state of nature is
not just a group of atomic individuals in which each is surrounded by a fence
with a sign announcing “Keep Out.” We are also persons who are
bound together by obligations to come to each other’s aid whenever this is
needed. Hence, the correct analogy to use in describing the relationship
of persons in the state of nature is not to a group of
individuals whose only relationship to one another is that they share the same
set of negative rights. It is to a family, a group of friends, villagers, neighbors and other small communities of persons bound together by positive rights and duties.
No comments:
Post a Comment