Subscribe to our monthly Philosophy Newsletter and get a Free copy of Understanding Philosophy: The Smart Student's Guide to Reading and Writing Philosophy
Dialogues on Rational Religion, Part 1
Scene of the dialogue: An undergraduate Philosophy of Religion honors class at a diverse American university.
Dialogue participants:
Professor Shanice Washington and students DeShawn Russell, Juanita Valdez, Jakub
Dabrowski, Robert Devereaux, Yoshiko Yamamoto, Makena Kalenjin.
1.1 What is rational religion?
Professor Washington: Let’s
begin our discussion on rational religion today with a question that is central
to the philosophy of religion: “Does God exist?”
Yoshiko: (raising her hand): Professor Washington, before we start, please
explain again what you mean by ‘rational religion’.
Prof: The phrase ‘rational religion’ is a variation of what the 18th
century philosopher David Hume referred to as ‘natural religion’[1]. It is the study of religion from the
standpoint of reasons and argument, not from revelation or personal religious
experiences.
When we ask the question
“Does God exist?” in our discussion, we are asking for reasons or evidence
for affirmative or negative answers to this question. We will not be asking for nonrational reports
of a “direct, personal awareness of God himself” (Rowe, 69).[2]
Robert: Is ‘nonrational’ synonymous with ‘irrational’?
Prof: Good question. And the answer
is ‘yes and no’. I realize that the word ‘irrational’ is often assumed to be a synonym
of ‘nonrational.’ But that is not how we will use it here.
The word ‘irrational’ is also used as a pejorative
evaluation of a belief. To call
someone’s belief ‘irrational’ is a way of expressing contempt or
disapproval.
But to call a belief ‘nonrational’
is not pejorative. It signifies a class of beliefs not based on reasons or
arguments. This classification does not imply
any evaluation at all, whether pejorative or complimentary.
Our dialogue here is about rational religion. Hence, following David Hume, we will restrict
ourselves to a critical examination of the traditional arguments for the
existence of God based on logic, reasons and evidence.
However, there is another
question we must ask before we start our investigations. Any idea what that question
that might be?
Jakub: Is it “Has everyone put away their cell phone?”
Prof: (laughing): Great question but it is not quite what I had in
mind. I will rephrase it: What important
ssumption are we making when we ask the question “Does God exist?”
(to be continued in part 2)
[1] David Hume, Dialogues
Concerning Natural Religion (1797); See also Laurence Houlgate, Understanding David Hume (HoulgateBooks.com, 2018).
[2]
Not all nonrational beliefs are religious. Here is a real-life personal example. About two days before I found a cat in my
house, I became suspicious that the neighbor’s cat might have gotten inside. There were traces in the house left by a cat,
such as cat hair on my favorite chair and an odd smell behind the washing
machine. But once I saw the cat hiding
under our bed after hearing a loud meowing sound, my suspicions were
confirmed.
My belief that there is a
cat in my house changed from a rational belief justified by evidence (cat hair,
fecal smell) to a nonrational belief based not on arguments or evidence, but on
a direct, personal experience of the cat. I no longer believed there was a cat in
the house, I now knew this.
Religious beliefs based on revelation alone are also nonrational. If someone says that they believe in the
existence of God because “in the world there are traces of God’s activity,”
they are giving a reason for God’s existence. But if the belief is a report of a direct
personal experience of God, this is nonrational in the same way that my knowledge
that there is a cat in the house is based on my direct experience of seeing a
cat under my bed.
No comments:
Post a Comment